Manure Management
and Moral Community
Paul B. Thompson
Purdue University
Les E. Lanyon
The Pennsylvania State University
Introduction
Different approaches to manure management run deeper than personal
preferences and technical expertise. Some of the current thinking on manure presumes that
the problem is simply a matter of finding cost-effective ways to raise animalshogs,
chickens or dairy cowsin a manner that limits discharge of nutrients into watersheds
at Environmental Protection Agency (EPA) or state environmental agency-approved levels.
Others find the fact that nutrient management has become problematic to be a symptom of a
deeper and more far-reaching predicament. One perspective emphasizes technological
solutions to the containment and disposal of nutrient wastes, while another emphasizes
policy solutions and community development. One set of approaches relies on farm-based
strategies for containing contaminants, while another emphasizes the local flow of crops,
that is limiting the space and time in which nutrients must recycle (Magdoff, Lanyon and
Leibhardt, 1997).
Farming's Traditional Ethic
In previous work Thompson (1994, 1995) has described the argument
between utilitarian and agrarian or communitarian philosophies of agriculture. A
philosophy of agriculture consists of beliefs about agriculture's purpose, and about the
ways of pursuing that purpose. It is normative in the sense that it stipulates, presumes
or implies norms or standards that would indicate whether any given system or approach to
farming and food production is good or bad, successful or not. It can be personal or
social. If social, a philosophy of agriculture states what farming is intended to
accomplish for society overall, irrespective of the personal goals that an individual farm
family might have. Utilitarian philosophy is guided by the following rule: act so as to
produce the greatest good for the greatest number. The utilitarian evaluates a farming
practice in light of the degree to which its benefits outweigh its costs. To the extent
that one can make a reasonable prediction of the consequences from any farming practice or
public policy, utilitarian philosophy supports case by case assessment and comparison. The
utilitarian maxim then directs us to choose the most efficient or optimal course of action
from all the available alternatives (Thompson, 1993; 1995). Agrarian or communitarian
philosophy of agriculture begins by describing an ideal. In America, the agrarian ideal is
characterized by multi-generational and diversified family farms, interacting with one
another and with the businesses and people of a small rural town. The agrarian ideal
provides a way of envisioning community itself; hence its philosophical meaning extends
beyond agriculture and rural life.
Prior to World War II, these two philosophies would have been unlikely
to spark much conflict in rural America. Agrarian philosophy is based on norms and
reciprocities among people who routinely interact with one another. The utilitarian ethic
governing farming dictates that market exchanges between free and informed individuals
provide reliable signals to guide production decisions. When the majority of animal
producers are operating diversified farms with extensive animal grazing, there is no
reason why these two philosophies should come into conflict with one another. However,
modern technology has created social relations between peoples distant from one another in
space and time. These relations challenge the conception of a moral community that is
implied by agrarian philosophy. Agrarian philosophy emphasizes reciprocal duties exchanged
by people who live in the same place over a period of generations. The new relations of
production challenge utilitarian philosophy by dramatically expanding the universe of
affected parties. An agricultural policy environment controlled by urban constituencies
challenges both views (Lanyon and Thompson, 1996).
Implications for Manure Management
At some point in the technological transformation of animal
production, philosophical differences lead to different perspectives on this situation.
For a utilitarian, there are new costs in the form of potential environmental impact and
the abatement of nuisances. The administrative structure for regulating environmental
impact also entails costs. Nevertheless, it may well be true that benefits (in the form of
lower food costs and increased income for industrial producers) outweigh environmental and
abatement costs. If so, someone operating with a utilitarian philosophy of agriculture may
feel entirely justified in pressing forward with more efficient intensive and industrial
technology. The key burden of proof will be to assess costs and benefits and to compare
the costs and benefits of relatively more industrialized production systems with the costs
and benefits of traditional systems.
For the agrarian, there is no compensation that will redress the
transformation of community that takes place when people who once regarded one another as
lifelong neighbors must now look at each other as potential litigators. The failure here
is ecological: soil and water eco-systems are challenged (Lanyon, 1995), but beyond that,
the community's ability to reproduce itself with any degree of historical of cultural
continuity is threatened. The reciprocities that form the basis of family and community
loyalty are transformed into legalisms that require government and expert mediation. The
fact that utilitarian thinking seems entirely unresponsive to this transformation simply
adds insult to injury.
Opportunities for Reconciliation
We have outlined a philosophical framework for interpreting the
challenges of manure management in light of a tension between two distinct philosophies of
agriculture. We are not claiming that this framework applies to every situation calling
for manure management. Whether or not the framework applies to any specific animal
production system or to any specific rural community depends on local conditions.
Nevertheless, increasing awareness of the philosophical dispute, rethinking the role of
technical experts, and becoming proactive with respect to moral community can improve the
situation in many instances.
Increasing Awareness.
People in conflict over
environmental issues have a working understanding of why others oppose their action.
Opponents may be thought of as ignorant of essential knowledge. They may be thought of as
people who "don't understand agriculture," or "live in the past."
Opponents may be characterized as lacking an understanding of ecology or of economics.
Opponents may also be described in moral terms as embracing values that are inimical to
property rights, personal freedom or sustainability. While we would not deny that there
are some circumstances in which this interpretation of environmental conflict is
warranted, we would argue that the tension between agrarian and utilitarian philosophy
does not, in itself, support such a pessimistic view of conflicts over manure management.
Both agrarian and utilitarian philosophies have deep roots in American culture. Each
embodies wisdom and each deserves respect. At the same time, each has been associated with
unsavory episodes in our past, so neither can be understood as an unalloyed solution to
all problems in American agriculture.
If opponents come to see one another as working from different
philosophical visions, a different working understanding of the conflict can emerge.
Opponents are not seen as necessarily ignorant or evil, but as having different goals and
as applying different burdens of proof. When one is dealing with reasonable opponents, it
becomes possible to search for partial solutions that satisfy all parties, with the
recognition that such agreements do not lay the foundation for future attacks.
Furthermore, it is possible to develop a more effective strategy for communicating or
negotiating with opponents. If one understands that opponents do not particularly care
about compensating costs and benefits, for example, one will not waste one's breath with
such arguments.
Redefining the Role of Expertise. Technical experts do
not usually advocate for utilitarian or agrarian philosophy. Yet science and engineering
prove far more useful to utilitarians, who see ethics as a future-oriented process of
comparing options, than to agrarians, who see ethics in terms of maintaining the integrity
of a moral community rooted in the past. The predictive capacity of technical expertise
enjoys a natural fit with the future orientation and cost comparing mentality of the
utilitarian. Those who take an agrarian approach might prefer activities that examine and
propagate a vision of cultural identity with the past. If utilitarian and agrarian
philosophies were to compete on a level playing field, advocates of each view would have
equal access to knowledge and public programs. As it stands, however, there are many
publicly funded scientists and technicians supporting work that can be deployed in a
utilitarian agriculture, and few public servants undertaking activities that would help
rural communities understand their past, their present identities, or providing tools to
help communities maintain a sense of community. This is a completely unintended bias in
public funding, but it is a bias nonetheless.
Moral Community.
As noted above, changes in production
and transportation technology have severed many of the practical ties between close
neighbors and especially between producers and the eventual consumers of animal products.
If one takes an agrarian viewpoint, this development is an evil in itself. If one takes a
utilitarian viewpoint, the problem consists in an unusual kind of market failure.
Consumers are unable to express their preferences for environmental quality or for a
particular form of social organization through their food purchases. Whichever view one
takes, there is an opportunity to experiment with new market structures.
Community supported agriculture (CSA) is one approach that attempts to
increase market-based feedback between producers and consumers, and the green marketing
strategy that has been developed in Pennsylvania is another. Economists have not always
been strong supporters of such efforts, largely because they involve cumbersome
institutional arrangements, and may not provide adequate price incentives for either
consumer or producer participation. Regulation by external experts is generally seen as a
surer way to bring about environmental improvements. However, if one sees these
experiments as attempts to close the gap between two philosophies of animal production, a
different rationale for attempting them begins to emerge.
A Milk Marketing Initiative
The Dairy Network Partnership
(DNP) in Pennsylvania, a coalition of
environmental, advocacy and educational organizations brought together to promote dairy
farm survival and environmental protection, is creating a milk marketing initiative
(MMI)
to link dairy farmers and consumers. This initiative is based on the adaptation of
Farm*A*Syst, a national farmstead assessment program, in central Lancaster County,
Pennsylvania under a USDA Water Quality Initiative Project. Although the original program
was intended as a self-awareness effort for farmers to protect their groundwater, it has
been adapted increase a sense of moral community with respect to water quality protection
assurance between dairy farmers and off-farm stakeholders. Farmstead water quality
protection evaluations result in scores for six areas on each dairy farm and an overall
farmstead score. Those farms with scores above the threshold are providing water quality
protection services that consumers value. This value is communicated through a premium
consumers pay on specially labeled milk. The premium will help to offset costs of water
quality protection incurred by dairy farmers providing those services. It will also
provide a positive and ongoing incentive for those who are not receiving the premium to
change practices in order to qualify.
The MMI differs from other cost-share programs organized under
Farm*A*Syst in that funds are allocated to the farms that are most likely to qualify for
the performance premium after implementation. Normally, cost-share funds go to farms with
the most serious water quality problems. The rationale for the normal policy is
utilitarian: make the most efficient use of cost-share funds by attacking the most
significant problems. The rationale for the MMI performance premium (and the reformulated
cost-share) is based on two notions that draw on an agrarian or communitarian conception
of moral community. First, water quality protection as a value-added service to society.
Second, consumers are brought into the loop. Their decisions affect environmental quality,
and help create a sound business planning mechanism for the implementation and maintenance
of water quality protection measure on dairy farms.
The ethical dilemma is to create a satisfactory reward framework for a
consumer that is sensitive to indirect goods or consequences. Consumers and the valuing
process thus are a focus of the water quality protection efforts we attempting to
implement. A revised formulation of ethical development is essential to this effort. A
community structure rather than an individualistic worldview encourages the discipline
(what we won t do that is within our capacity) that is critical to the success of the
MMI.
We hope that through transparent standards and evaluation techniques we can forge an
ethical community that is sustained through information rather than face-to-face
interaction. This ability to act upon the distributed consequences of our actions for
others and nature is the essence of the environmental message for living within our
present and future community. The MMI is simply a mechanism to promote this message and to
demonstrate its implementation in a concrete way.
References
Lanyon, L. E. 1995. Does nitrogen cycle? Changes in the spatial dynamics of
nitrogen following the industrialization of nitrogen fixation. J. Prod. Agric.
8:70-78.
Lanyon, L.E. and P. B. Thompson. 1996. Changes in farm production. p. 15-23 in
Proc. Animal Agriculture and the Environment. December 11-13, 1996. Rochester, NY.
Northeast Regional Agricultural Engineering Service, Ithaca, NY.
Magdoff, F., L. E. Lanyon and W. C.
Leibhardt. 1997. Nutrient cycling in a sustainable
agriculture. Adv. Agron. 60:1-73.
Thompson, P.B. 1993. "Animals in the Agrarian Ideal," Journal of
Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 6 (special supplement 1): 36-49.
Thompson, P.B. 1995. The Spirit of the Soil: Agriculture and Environmental Ethics, New
York and London: Routledge Publishing Co.
Thompson, P. B. 1996. "Conceptions of Sustainability and the Industrialization of
Livestock Farming," LUDUS VITALIS: Revista de Filosofía de las Ciencias de la
Vida Número especial 2, 1997, (Memorias de Tecnología, Desarrollo Económico y
Sustenatabilidad, la IX Conferencia Internacional de la Society for Philosophy and
Technology, Puebla, Mexico,) pp. 143-156.
To Top |